green numbers give full details.
|
back to list of philosophers
|
expand these ideas
Ideas of Kathrin Koslicki, by Text
[German, fl. 2008, Professor at the University of Colorado, Boulder.]
1997
|
Isolation and Non-arbitrary Division
|
|
p.424
|
17439
|
There is no deep reason why we count carrots but not asparagus
|
2.2
|
p.411
|
17433
|
We can still count squares, even if they overlap
|
2.2
|
p.413
|
17434
|
We struggle to count branches and waves because our concepts lack clear boundaries
|
2.2
|
p.416
|
17435
|
Objects do not naturally form countable units
|
2.2
|
p.417
|
17436
|
We talk of snow as what stays the same, when it is a heap or drift or expanse
|
2008
|
The Structure of Objects
|
Info
|
p.6
|
14497
|
The clay is just a part of the statue (its matter); the rest consists of its form or structure
|
Intro
|
p.4
|
13266
|
Wholes in modern mereology are intended to replace sets, so they closely resemble them
|
Intro
|
p.5
|
14495
|
I aim to put the notion of structure or form back into the concepts of part, whole and object
|
Intro
|
p.6
|
14496
|
Structure or form are right at the centre of modern rigorous modes of enquiry
|
2.2
|
p.25
|
14498
|
For three-dimensionalist parthood must be a three-place relation, including times
|
3.1
|
p.45
|
14500
|
Wholes are entities distinct from their parts, and have different properties
|
3.2.3.1
|
p.55
|
14501
|
'Categorical' properties exist in the actual world, and 'hypothetical' properties in other worlds
|
4.2.2
|
p.115
|
13264
|
If a whole is just a structure, a dinner party wouldn't need the guests to turn up
|
5.1
|
p.93
|
13258
|
The 'aggregative' objections says mereology gets existence and location of objects wrong
|
7.2.11
|
p.192
|
13281
|
Wholes are not just their parts; a whole is an entity distinct from the proper parts
|
7.2.12
|
p.195
|
13283
|
The parts may be the same type as the whole, like a building made of buildings
|
7.2.7.2
|
p.179
|
13280
|
Statue and clay differ in modal and temporal properties, and in constitution
|
7.2.7.2 n17
|
p.179
|
13279
|
There are at least six versions of constitution being identity
|
8.2
|
p.202
|
13284
|
Should vernacular classifications ever be counted as natural kind terms?
|
8.3.1
|
p.204
|
13285
|
Natural kinds support inductive inferences, from previous samples to the next one
|
8.4.1
|
p.211
|
13286
|
There are apparently no scientific laws concerning biological species
|
8.4.1
|
p.212
|
13287
|
Concepts for species are either intrinsic structure, or relations like breeding or ancestry
|
8.6.2
|
p.231
|
14504
|
The Kripke/Putnam approach to natural kind terms seems to give them excessive stability
|
9.3.1 n6
|
p.241
|
14505
|
Some questions concern mathematical entities, rather than whole structures
|
9.3.2
|
p.242
|
14506
|
'Roses are red; therefore, roses are colored' seems truth-preserving, but not valid in a system
|
9.3.2 n8
|
p.243
|
13288
|
Consequence is truth-preserving, either despite substitutions, or in all interpretations
|
9.6
|
p.259
|
13289
|
Structures have positions, constituent types and number, and some invariable parts
|
2012
|
Essence, Necessity and Explanation
|
13.1
|
p.188
|
15110
|
An essence and what merely follow from it are distinct
|
13.1
|
p.189
|
15111
|
In demonstration, the explanatory order must mirror the causal order of the phenomena
|
13.2
|
p.190
|
15112
|
If an object exists, then its essential properties are necessary
|
13.3.1
|
p.198
|
15113
|
Individuals are perceived, but demonstration and definition require universals
|
13.3.1
|
p.199
|
15115
|
In a demonstration the middle term explains, by being part of the definition
|
13.3.1
|
p.200
|
15118
|
A successful Aristotelian 'definition' is what sciences produces after an investigation
|
13.3.1
|
p.200
|
15116
|
Essences cause necessary features, and definitions describe those necessary features
|
13.3.1 n10
|
p.198
|
15114
|
Discovering the Aristotelian essence of thunder will tell us why thunder occurs
|
13.3.1 n15
|
p.200
|
15117
|
Greek uses the same word for 'cause' and 'explanation'
|
2012
|
Varieties of Ontological Dependence
|
7.4
|
p.196
|
17309
|
For Fine, essences are propositions true because of identity, so they are just real definitions
|
7.4
|
p.198
|
17311
|
Real definitions don't just single out a thing; they must also explain its essence
|
7.4
|
p.199
|
17312
|
It is more explanatory if you show how a number is constructed from basic entities and relations
|
7.4 n13
|
p.200
|
17313
|
Modern views want essences just to individuate things across worlds and times
|
7.5 n25
|
p.211
|
17314
|
The relata of grounding are propositions or facts, but for dependence it is objects and their features
|
7.6
|
p.212
|
17315
|
We need a less propositional view of essence, and so must distinguish it clearly from real definitions
|
7.6
|
p.212
|
17316
|
We can abstract to a dependent entity by blocking out features of its bearer
|
7.6
|
p.213
|
17317
|
A good explanation captures the real-world dependence among the phenomena
|