1980 | Identity and Essence |
p.119 | 15834 | Brody bases sortal essentialism on properties required throughout something's existence | |
Full Idea: Brody bases sortal essentialism on the notion of a property that an individual must possess throughout its existence if it possesses it at any time in its existence. | |||
From: report of Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980]) by Penelope Mackie - How Things Might Have Been 7.1 | |||
A reaction: Brody tends to treat categories as properties, which I dislike. How do you assess 'must' here? A person may possess a mole throughout life without it being essential. |
p.119 | 11895 | A sortal essence is a property which once possessed always possessed | |
Full Idea: Brody bases sortal essentialism on the notion of a property that an individual must possess throughout its existence if it possesses it at any time in its existence. ...'Once an F, always an F'. ...Being a parrot is not a temporary occupation. | |||
From: report of Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980]) by Penelope Mackie - How Things Might Have Been 7.1 | |||
A reaction: Hm. Would being less than fifty metres tall qualify as a sortal essence, for a giraffe or a uranium rod? If there is one thing an essential property should be, it is important. How do we assess importance? By explanatory power! Watch this space. |
p.132 | 12141 | Maybe essential properties are those which determine a natural kind? | |
Full Idea: We can advance the thesis that all essential properties either determine a natural kind or are part of an essential property that does determine a natural kind. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980]) | |||
A reaction: A useful clear statement of the view. I am opposed to it, because I take it to be of the essence of Socrates that he is philosophical, but humans are not essentially philosophical, and philosophers are unlikely to be a natural kind. |
1.2 | p.9 | 12130 | a and b share all properties; so they share being-identical-with-a; so a = b |
Full Idea: Suppose that a and b have all of their properties in common. a certainly has the property of-being-identical-with-a. So, by supposition, does b. Then a = b. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 1.2) | |||
A reaction: Brody defends this argument, and seems to think that it proves the identity of indiscernibles. As far as I can see it totally begs the question, since we can only assume that both have the property of being-identical-with-a if we have assumed a = b. |
3 | p.43 | 12132 | Indiscernibility is a necessary and sufficient condition for identity |
Full Idea: Enduring objects should be taken as fundamental in an ontology, and for all such objects indiscernibility is both a necessary and sufficient condition for identity. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 3) | |||
A reaction: Brody offers a substantial defence, but I don't find it plausible. Apart from Black's well known twin spheres example (Idea 10195), discernibility is relative to the powers of the observer. Two similar people in the mist aren't thereby identical. |
4.1 | p.80 | 12135 | Interrupted objects have two first moments of existence, which could be two beginnings |
Full Idea: If 'beginning of existence' meant 'first moment of existence after a period of nonexistence', then objects with interrupted existence have two beginnings of existence. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 4.1) | |||
A reaction: One might still maintain that the first beginning was essential to the object, since that is the event that defined it - and that would clarify the reason why we are supposed to think the origins are essential. I say the origin explains it. |
5.4 | p.103 | 12137 | De re essentialism standardly says all possible objects identical with a have a's essential properties |
Full Idea: To say that an object a has a property P essentially is to say that it has P, and in all of certain worlds (all possible, all in which something identical with it exists, ...) the object identical with it has P. This is the standard de re interpretation. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 5.4) | |||
A reaction: This view always has to be qualified by excluding trivially necessary properties, but that exclusion shows clearly that the notion of essential is more concerned with non-triviality than it is with necessity. |
5.4 | p.111 | 12138 | Identity across possible worlds is prior to rigid designation |
Full Idea: Identity across possible worlds is prior to rigid designation. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 5.4) | |||
A reaction: An interesting view. We might stipulate that any possible Aristotle is 'our Aristotle', but you would still need criteria for deciding which possible Aristotle's would qualify. Long-frozen Aristotles, stupid Aristotles, alien Aristotle's, deformed... |
5.6 | p.128 | 12139 | Mereological essentialism says that every part that ensures the existence is essential |
Full Idea: Mereological essentialism (whose leading advocate is Chisholm) says that for every x and y, if x is ever part of y, then y is necessarily such that x is part of y at any time that y exists. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 5.6) | |||
A reaction: This sounds implausible, especially given the transitivity of parthood. Not only are the planks that constitute Theseus's Ship now essential to it, but all the parts of the planks, every last chip, are as well. |
5.6 | p.131 | 12140 | Modern emphasis is on properties had essentially; traditional emphasis is on sort-defining properties |
Full Idea: The modern emphasis has been on the connection between essential properties and the properties that an object must have essentially. But traditionally there is also the connection between essential properties and the sort of thing that it is. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 5.6) | |||
A reaction: These are the modal essence and the definitional essence. My view is that he has missed out a crucial third (Aristotelian) view, which is that essences are explanatory. This third view can subsume the other two. |
6 | p.135 | 12142 | Essentially, a has P, always had P, must have had P, and has never had a future without P |
Full Idea: 'a has property P essentially' means 'a has P, a always had P, there is no possible past in which P exists without P, and there is no moment of time at which a has had P and at which there is a possible future in which a exists without P' | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 6) | |||
A reaction: This is Brody's own final account of essentialism. This is a carefully qualified form of the view that essential properties are, on the whole, the necessary properties, which view I take to be fundamentally mistaken. |
6.1 | p.136 | 12143 | An object having a property essentially is equivalent to its having it necessarily |
Full Idea: An object having a property essentially is equivalent to its having it necessarily. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 6.1) | |||
A reaction: This strikes me as blatantly false. Personally I am toying with the very unorthodox view that essential properties are not at all necessary, and that something can retain its identity while changing its essential character. A philosopher with Alzheimers. |
6.3 | p.152 | 12144 | Essentialism is justified if the essential properties of things explain their other properties |
Full Idea: The reasonableness of the essentialist hypothesis will be proportional to the extent that we can, as a result, use a's possession of P to explain a's other properties, ...and there is an inability to explain otherwise why a has P. | |||
From: Baruch Brody (Identity and Essence [1980], 6.3) | |||
A reaction: Brody as a rather liberal notion of properties. I would hope that we can do rather more than explain a's non-essential properties. If the non-essential properties were entailed by the essential ones, would they not then also be essential? |