green numbers give full details.
|
back to list of philosophers
|
expand these ideas
Ideas of Edouard Machery, by Text
[French, fl. 2009, Professor at the University of Pittsburgh.]
2009
|
Doing Without Concepts
|
1.1
|
p.14
|
18563
|
By 'concept' psychologists mean various sorts of representation or structure
|
Intro
|
p.4
|
18557
|
Psychologists treat concepts as long-term knowledge bodies which lead to judgements
|
Intro
|
p.4
|
18558
|
Concept theorists examine their knowledge, format, processes, acquisition and location
|
Intro
|
p.6
|
18559
|
Philosophy is empty if it does not in some way depend on matters of fact
|
1.1
|
p.8
|
18560
|
Psychologist treat concepts as categories
|
1.1
|
p.9
|
18561
|
We can identify a set of cognitive capacities which are 'higher order'
|
1.1
|
p.13
|
18562
|
Connectionists cannot distinguish concept-memories from their background, or the processes
|
1.3.2
|
p.19
|
18564
|
Do categories store causal knowledge, or typical properties, or knowledge of individuals?
|
1.4.1
|
p.22
|
18565
|
There may be ad hoc categories, such as the things to pack in your suitcase for a trip
|
1.4.1
|
p.24
|
18566
|
Concepts should contain working memory, not long-term, because they control behaviour
|
1.4.3
|
p.26
|
18567
|
In the philosophy of psychology, concepts are usually introduced as constituents of thoughts
|
2.1.2
|
p.33
|
18569
|
In philosophy theories of concepts explain how our propositional attitudes have content
|
2.1.3
|
p.33
|
18570
|
There may be several ways to individuate things like concepts
|
3
|
p.52
|
18573
|
For each category of objects (such as 'dog') an individual seems to have several concepts
|
3.2.1
|
p.58
|
18574
|
Concepts for categorisation and for induction may be quite different
|
3.2.3
|
p.61
|
18575
|
The concepts for a class typically include prototypes, and exemplars, and theories
|
3.3.1
|
p.65
|
18584
|
One hybrid theory combines a core definition with a prototype for identification
|
3.3.2
|
p.68
|
18585
|
Heterogeneous concepts might have conflicting judgements, where hybrid theories will not
|
3.3.4
|
p.74
|
18577
|
The word 'grandmother' may be two concepts, with a prototype and a definition
|
4
|
p.76
|
18587
|
The theory account is sometimes labelled as 'knowledge' or 'explanation' in approach
|
4
|
p.76
|
18578
|
Concepts as definitions was rejected, and concepts as prototypes, exemplars or theories proposed
|
4
|
p.77
|
18588
|
Concept theories aim at their knowledge, processes, format, acquisition, and location
|
4.1.1
|
p.78
|
18589
|
For behaviourists concepts are dispositions to link category members to names
|
4.1.3
|
p.80
|
18591
|
Classical theory can't explain facts like typical examples being categorised quicker
|
4.1.3
|
p.80
|
18590
|
Classical theory implies variety in processing times, but this does not generally occur
|
4.1.4
|
p.82
|
18583
|
Many categories don't seem to have a definition
|
4.1.4
|
p.82
|
18592
|
The concepts OBJECT or AGENT may be innate
|
4.2.1
|
p.84
|
18594
|
Knowing typical properties of things is especially useful in induction
|
4.2.1 n25
|
p.83
|
18593
|
The term 'prototype' is used for both typical category members, and the representation
|
4.2.3
|
p.90
|
18595
|
Prototype theories are based on computation of similarities with the prototype
|
4.2.4
|
p.91
|
18596
|
Prototype theorists don't tell us how we select the appropriate prototype
|
4.3.1
|
p.93
|
18597
|
Concepts as exemplars are based on the knowledge of properties of each particular
|
4.3.1
|
p.94
|
18598
|
Exemplar theories need to explain how the relevant properties are selected from a multitude of them
|
4.3.3
|
p.98
|
18599
|
In practice, known examples take priority over the rest of the set of exemplars
|
4.4.1
|
p.101
|
18600
|
Theory Theory says category concepts are knowledge stores explaining membership
|
4.4.1
|
p.103
|
18601
|
Theory Theory says concepts are explanatory knowledge, and concepts form domains
|
4.4.4
|
p.106
|
18602
|
A thing is classified if its features are likely to be generated by that category's causal laws
|
4.5.3
|
p.117
|
18603
|
Maybe concepts are not the typical properties, but the ideal properties
|
5.1.1
|
p.122
|
18604
|
Are quick and slow categorisation the same process, or quite different?
|
6.3.2
|
p.171
|
18605
|
It is more efficient to remember the prototype, than repeatedly create it from exemplars
|
6.4.1
|
p.174
|
18606
|
The prototype view predicts that typical members are easier to categorise
|
6.5.1
|
p.183
|
18607
|
Theory theorists rely on best explanation, rather than on similarities
|
6.5.1
|
p.185
|
18608
|
If categorisation is not by similarity, it seems to rely on what properties things might have
|
7.1.1
|
p.197
|
18609
|
Psychologists use 'induction' as generalising a property from one category to another
|
7.1.1
|
p.198
|
18610
|
'Ampliative' induction infers that all members of a category have a feature found in some of them
|
8
|
p.220
|
18611
|
We should abandon 'concept', and just use 'prototype', 'exemplar' and 'theory'
|
8.1.3
|
p.227
|
18612
|
Americans are more inclined to refer causally than the Chinese are
|
8.2.1
|
p.234
|
18613
|
Artifacts can be natural kinds, when they are the object of historical enquiry
|
8.2.3
|
p.237
|
18614
|
Vertical arguments say eliminate a term if it picks out different natural kinds in different theories
|
8.2.3
|
p.237
|
18615
|
Horizontal arguments say eliminate a term if it fails to pick out a natural kind
|
8.2.3
|
p.239
|
18616
|
If a term doesn't pick out a kind, keeping it may block improvements in classification
|