green numbers give full details.
|
back to list of philosophers
|
expand these ideas
Ideas of JC Beall / G Restall, by Text
[Australian, fl. 2005, Professors at the Universities of Connecticut and Melbourne]
Intro
|
p.1
|
10688
|
'Equivocation' is when terms do not mean the same thing in premises and conclusion
|
2
|
p.4
|
10689
|
A step is a 'material consequence' if we need contents as well as form
|
2
|
p.5
|
10690
|
Formal logic is invariant under permutations, or devoid of content, or gives the norms for thought
|
2
|
p.7
|
10695
|
Logical consequence is either necessary truth preservation, or preservation based on interpretation
|
3
|
p.6
|
10691
|
Logical consequence needs either proofs, or absence of counterexamples
|
3
|
p.6
|
10693
|
Models are mathematical structures which interpret the non-logical primitives
|
3
|
p.6
|
10692
|
Hilbert proofs have simple rules and complex axioms, and natural deduction is the opposite
|
4
|
p.8
|
10696
|
A 'logical truth' (or 'tautology', or 'theorem') follows from empty premises
|
2.1
|
p.8
|
13232
|
Logic studies arguments, not formal languages; this involves interpretations
|
2.1
|
p.12
|
13233
|
Propositions commit to content, and not to any way of spelling it out
|
2.2
|
p.12
|
13234
|
The view of logic as knowing a body of truths looks out-of-date
|
2.2
|
p.13
|
13235
|
Logic studies consequence; logical truths are consequences of everything, or nothing
|
2.2
|
p.13
|
13236
|
Logical truth is much more important if mathematics rests on it, as logicism claims
|
2.4
|
p.16
|
13237
|
Preface Paradox affirms and denies the conjunction of propositions in the book
|
2.5
|
p.19
|
13238
|
Syllogisms are only logic when they use variables, and not concrete terms
|
2.5
|
p.21
|
13239
|
Judgement is always predicating a property of a subject
|
3.2
|
p.29
|
13240
|
A sentence follows from others if they always model it
|
4.2.1
|
p.40
|
13241
|
The model theory of classical predicate logic is mathematics
|
5.2
|
p.53
|
13243
|
Excluded middle must be true for some situation, not for all situations
|
5.2
|
p.53
|
13242
|
It's 'relevantly' valid if all those situations make it true
|
5.2
|
p.53
|
13244
|
Relevant necessity is always true for some situation (not all situations)
|
5.3.3
|
p.55
|
13245
|
Relevant consequence says invalidity is the conclusion not being 'in' the premises
|
5.4
|
p.55
|
13246
|
Relevant logic does not abandon classical logic
|
5.5.3
|
p.57
|
13247
|
A truthmaker is an object which entails a sentence
|
5.5.4
|
p.58
|
13248
|
We can rest truth-conditions on situations, rather than on possible worlds
|
6.1.2
|
p.64
|
13249
|
(∀x)(A v B) |- (∀x)A v (∃x)B) is valid in classical logic but invalid intuitionistically
|
7.1
|
p.75
|
13250
|
Free logic terms aren't existential; classical is non-empty, with referring names
|
7.4
|
p.79
|
13252
|
Some truths have true negations
|
8
|
p.88
|
13253
|
There are several different consequence relations
|
8
|
p.91
|
13255
|
Relevant logic may reject transitivity
|
8
|
p.91
|
13254
|
A doesn't imply A - that would be circular
|